Stevan Harnad (2001) The Ubiquity of Physics (and the Physics-independence of Computation). Psycoloquy: 12(041) Symbolism Connectionism (8)

Volume: 12 (next, prev) Issue: 041 (next, prev) Article: 8 (next prev first) Alternate versions: ASCII Summary
Topic:
Article:
PSYCOLOQUY (ISSN 1055-0143) is sponsored by the American Psychological Association (APA).
Psycoloquy 12(041): The Ubiquity of Physics (and the Physics-independence of Computation)

THE UBIQUITY OF PHYSICS (AND THE PHYSICS-INDEPENDENCE OF COMPUTATION)
Reply to Dietrich on Harnad on Symbolism-Connectionism

Stevan Harnad
Department of Electronics and Computer Science
University of Southampton
Highfield, Southampton
SO17 1BJ
United Kingdom
http://www.cogsci.soton.ac.uk/~harnad/

harnad@cogsci.soton.ac.uk

Abstract

Dietrich (2001) thinks everything is computational. If so, then nothing is meant by saying something is computational. But it is not so. Flying is not computational. Heating is not computational. By the same, thinking in not (all) computational.

    REPRINT OF: Harnad, S. (1993). Harnad's response to Dietrich.
    Think 2: 12-78 (Special Issue on "Connectionism versus Symbolism"
    D.M.W. Powers & P.A. Flach, eds.).
    http://cwis.kub.nl/~fdl/research/ti/docs/think/2-1/index.stm

1. If Dietrich (2001) endorses my empirical approach, is there anything left to quarrel about? Or has he too changed the subject? I define computation as syntactic symbol manipulation; Dietrich sees it as the execution of recursive functions. As far as I know, these two are equivalent. Dietrich says every process is a computation, but that this is not vacuous. If he means every process is describable by computation (as it is by English sentences -- another form of computation), I think this is true (I do subscribe to the Church/Turing Thesis), but irrelevant. For the purpose of computationalism (or so I thought) was to distinguish cognitive systems from, say, planetary systems, fluids and electrons (to pick some basic physical systems), or from furnaces, cars and planes (to pick some engineering systems). If all of these dynamical systems are computational systems, then so is the brain, of course, and there seems to be nothing worth disagreeing about -- but we're no closer to knowing what's special about cognitive systems.

2. But is every dynamical process computation? Is there no longer a difference between a furnace and a virtual furnace? I think I can still espy one: The furnace really gets hot, whereas the virtual furnace is just a bunch of symbols that are systematically interpretable as if something was getting hot. 'Getting hot,' in other words, is not a computational process but a physical process; in particular, unlike computation, it is not implementation-independent. So there's hope for computationalism. For if it is not true that every process is just computation, but only that every process is simulable by computation, then we can still ask whether cognition is something computation is rather than just something computation can simulate or describe; in other words, whether cognition is just implementation-independent syntactic symbol manipulation or something more.

3. And it turns out that you don't have to turn to the halting problem to falsify this nonvacuous hypothesis: Searle's (1980) Chinese Room Argument suffices; or, if that's not enough to persuade you, consider the kinds of obstacles the symbol grounding problem raises for the hypothesis that thinking is just symbol manipulation (Harnad 1990a,b). I can't see Dietrich's difficulty with understanding what is meant by 'syntactic rules operating only on [symbol] shapes' [which, like the shape of the physical states in the simulated furnace, are arbitrary in relation to what the symbols can be systematically interpreted as meaning -- see Boyle (2001) on pattern matching], but I would be especially interested to hear more about the 'commonplace' that computation is 'fully semantical': Does this mean that a simulated furnace is not just squiggles and squoggles that are systematically interpretable by us as if they were getting hot? Do they somehow embody that interpretation autonomously, in the way that the sentences in a book, say, do not?

4. I think Dietrich may be selling semantics short here: For me, at any rate, there's only one kind of meaning, and that's the kind that occurs in the heads of conscious systems (Harnad 2001b). When I say some system or part of a system means 'the cat is on the mat,' I really mean the system consciously means it, the way I do when I think it. Cognition, after all, is thinking, isn't it? And thinking is conscious thinking (or at least going on in the head of a conscious thinker). So, in order not to beg the question about whether or not computation is indeed 'fully semantical,' it will have to be shown that the computational system consciously means what it is (otherwise only) systematically interpretable by us as meaning.

5. Let me hasten to add that this is a much taller order than I undertake in trying to ground symbols in TTT capacity: Just as immunity to Searle's argument cannot guarantee mentality, so groundedness cannot do so either. It only immunizes against the objection that the connection between the symbol and what it is about is merely in the mind of the interpreter. A TTT-indistinguishable system could still fail to have a mind; there may still be no meaning in there. Unfortunately, however, that is an ontic state of affairs that is forever epistemically inaccessible to us: We cannot be any the wiser.

NOTES

[1] Dietrich misunderstands my points about possible performance limitations of ungrounded symbol systems in general [apart from their cognitive ambitions]; that was just a conjecture, on which nothing else I say depends; and far from wanting to give reasons why parallelism is essential for anything cognitive, I chose transduction, not parallelism, as my motivated candidate for this essential role.

REFERENCES

Boyle, C.F. (2001) Transduction and degree of grounding. PSYCOLOQUY 12(036) http://www.cogsci.soton.ac.uk/cgi/psyc/newpsy?12.036

Dietrich, E. (1990) `Computationalism'. In: Social Epistemology 4: 135-154.

Dietrich, E. (2001) The ubiquity of computation. PSYCOLOQUY 12(040) http://www.cogsci.soton.ac.uk/cgi/psyc/newpsy?12.040

Harnad, S. (1990a) "The Symbol Grounding Problem". Physica D 42: 335-346. http://cogprints.soton.ac.uk/documents/disk0/00/00/06/15/index.html

Harnad, Stevan (1990b) Against Computational Hermeneutics. Social Epistemology 4:167-172. http://cogprints.soton.ac.uk/documents/disk0/00/00/15/76/index.html

Harnad, S. (2001) Grounding symbols in the analog world with neural nets -- A hybrid model. PSYCOLOQUY 12(034) http://www.cogsci.soton.ac.uk/cgi/psyc/newpsy?12.034

Harnad, Stevan (2001a) Minds, Machines and Turing: The Indistinguishability of Indistinguishables. Journal of Logic, Language, and Information 9(4):425-445. http://cogprints.soton.ac.uk/documents/disk0/00/00/16/16/index.html

Harnad, Stevan (2001b) No Easy Way Out. The Sciences 41(2):36-42. http://cogprints.soton.ac.uk/documents/disk0/00/00/16/24/index.html

Searle, J. R. (1980) "Minds, brains and programs." Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3: 417-424. http://www.cogsci.soton.ac.uk/bbs/Archive/bbs.searle2.html http://www.bbsonline.org/documents/a/00/00/04/84/index.html


Volume: 12 (next, prev) Issue: 041 (next, prev) Article: 8 (next prev first) Alternate versions: ASCII Summary
Topic:
Article: