Summary of PSYCOLOQUY topic Consciousness

Topic:
Title & AuthorAbstract
3(15) ON THE EVOLUTION OF CONSCIOUSNESS AND LANGUAGE
Target Article on Consciousness
Bruce Bridgeman
Dept. of Psychology
Kerr Hall UCSC
Santa Cruz, Ca. 95064
(408) 459-4005

bruceb@cats.ucsc.edu
Abstract: Psychology can be based on plans, internally held images of achievement that organize the stimulus-response links of traditional psychology. The hierarchical structure of plans must be produced, held, assigned priorities, and monitored. Consciousness is the operation of the plan-executing mechanism, enabling behavior to be driven by plans rather than immediate environmental contingencies. The mechanism unpacks a single internally held idea into a series of actions. New in this paper is the proposal that language uses this mechanism for communication, unpacking an idea into a series of articulatory acts. Language comprehension uses the plan-monitoring mechanism to pack a series of linguistic events into an idea. Recursive processing results from monitoring one's own speech. Neurophysiologically, the planning mechanism is identified with higher-order motor control.

Keywords: consciousness, language, plans, motivation, evolution, motor system

3(17) ROBOTS NEED TO BE CONSCIOUS
Commentary on Bridgeman on Consciousness
John H. Andreae
Dept of Electrical & Electronic Engineering
University of Canterbury
Christchurch New Zealand

andreae@elec.canterbury.ac.nz
Abstract: This commentary supports Bridgeman's general thesis. I promote the use of robot design and simulation in psychological argument, and show that there are good engineering reasons for trying to work out what is needed to build a robot that is aware of what it is doing. Acceptance of Bridgeman's thesis that consciousness is the operation of a plan-executing mechanism should enable one to get down to the design of appropriate mechanisms for making plans, storing them, executing them and monitoring them.

Keywords: consciousness, language, plans, motivation, evolution, motor system.

3(18) PLANS AND THE STRUCTURE OF CONSCIOUSNESS
Reply to Andreae on Bridgeman on Consciousness
Bruce Bridgeman
Dept. of Psychology
Kerr Hall UCSC
Santa Cruz, Ca. 95064
(408) 459-4005

bruceb@cats.ucsc.edu
Abstract: If plans are to become the highest level of control in nervous systems, it is important to think carefully about what they imply. I suggested that there need be no box labelled "consciousness" in the brain, because consciousness is the name we give to the process of executing plans.

Keywords: consciousness, language, plans, motivation, evolution, motor system

3(19) THE SOCIAL ROLE OF CONSCIOUSNESS
Commentary on Bridgeman on Consciousness
Horace Barlow
Physiological Laboratory
Downing St
Cambridge CB2 3EG, UK

AECP1@PHOENIX.CAMBRIDGE.AC.UK
Abstract: Bridgeman's article is important but is only a single step in the right direction. It must also be accepted that the complete psychology of an individual could only portray a shadow of their full personality. It is the reportability of our plans that makes links between individuals possible, and that it is the consequences and characteristics of these links that complete our personalities.

Keywords: consciousness, language, plans, motivation, evolution, motor system

3(20) THE SOCIAL BOOTSTRAPPING OF HUMAN CONSCIOUSNESS
Reply to Barlow on Bridgeman on Consciousness
Bruce Bridgeman
Dept. of Psychology
Kerr Hall UCSC
Santa Cruz, Ca. 95064
(408) 459-4005

bruceb@cats.ucsc.edu
Abstract: Barlow (1992) has identified a crucial prerequisite for self-consciousness. I concur with most of his commentary adding only a few elaborations.

Keywords: consciousness, language, plans, motivation, evolution, motor system.

3(21) ON UNCONSCIOUS BABIES AND DREAMLESS SLEEP
Commentary on Bridgeman on Consciousness
Richard Fielding
Behavioural Sciences Unit
University of Hong Kong.

HRMRFIR@HKUCC.HKU.HK
Abstract: Bridgeman's plan unpacking hypothesis is attractive as an explanation of consciousness but does not clearly address issues of intent, development, and altered states of consciousness. An elaboration focussing on these issues is needed.

Keywords: consciousness, language, plans, motivation, evolution, motor system.

3(22) THE ONTOGENY OF CONSCIOUSNESS
Reply to Fielding on Bridgeman on Consciousness
Bruce Bridgeman
Dept. of Psychology
Kerr Hall UCSC
Santa Cruz, Ca. 95064
(408) 459-4005

bruceb@cats.ucsc.edu
Abstract: I first address some definitional issues then examine the the marginal cases Fielding proffers as examples.

Keywords: consciousness, language, plans, motivation, evolution, motor system

3(23) SOME COMMONSENSE ABOUT CONSCIOUSNESS
Commentary on Bridgeman on Consciousness
Donald Laming
University of Cambridge
Department of Experimental Psychology
Downing Street
Cambridge, England CB2 3EB
(0223)-333565

drjl@uk.ac.cam.phx
Abstract: Consciousness has been the subject of much misunderstanding. Bridgeman (1992) offers a strategic insight when he declares (2.9) "It is meaningless to look for a box labelled "consciousness" in a brain model, or to try to localize it in the brain's anatomy. The operations that make us conscious occur in the context of controlling behavior." Nevertheless, his analysis is neither so simple nor so natural as it might be. This commentary reassembles the elements of the target article in a more compelling interrelationship.

Keywords: consciousness, language, plans, motivation, evolution, motor system.

3(24) QUALIA AND MEMORY
Response to Laming on Bridgeman on Consciousness
Bruce Bridgeman
Dept. of Psychology
Kerr Hall UCSC
Santa Cruz, Ca. 95064
(408) 459-4005

bruceb@cats.ucsc.edu
Abstract: Laming (1992) identifies an ambiguity in my target article, where I associate consciousness with two functions -- planning on one hand and episodic memory on the other. I clarify these relationships by differentiating between the origin and the functioning of consciousness.

Keywords: consciousness, language, plans, motivation, evolution, motor system.

3(25) FROM PLANS TO MEDIATED ACTIONS
Commentary on Bridgeman on Consciousness
Jacob M.J. Murre
MRC Applied Psychology Unit
15 Chaucer Road
Cambridge CB2 2EF
United Kingdom

Jaap.Murre@MRC-APU.CAM.AC.UK
Abstract: We argue that evolution has supported a combinatorial explosion in the possibilities for action in man as a result of evolutionary pressure from three distinct sources: communication, learning, and mediated action. The latter is intimately related to language use and planning and hinges on the incorporation of plans conveyed by others into once own actions. The individual development of sophisticated planning ability is a complex process of gradual internalization of sociocultural entities that come increasingly to mediate actions. The most significant research question concerns the process of mediation rather than the structure of plans or other mediating entities and therefore propose that mediated actions, rather than plans, occupy center stage in psychology.

Keywords: consciousness, language, plans, motivation, evolution, motor system

3(26) LANGUAGE AND PLANS IN THE ANALYSIS OF CONSCIOUSNESS
Reply to Murre on Bridgeman on Consciousness
Bruce Bridgeman
Dept. of Psychology
Kerr Hall UCSC
Santa Cruz, Ca. 95064
(408) 459-4005

bruceb@cats.ucsc.edu
Abstract: In my target article I suggest that sequential articulation of action and articulation of language arise from the same mechanism. Murre's assertion of a "mediated action" linking sophisticated language and planning creates more problems than it solves.

Keywords: consciousness, language, plans, motivation, evolution, motor system

3(27) PLANS AND THE EVOLUTION OF LANGUAGE
Commentary on Bridgeman on Consciousness
William Noble
Psychology Department
University of New England
Armidale, NSW, Australia

wnoble@metz.une.oz.au (William Noble)
Abstract: Bridgeman's (1992) focus on planning as symptomatic of human life makes good sense. The idea that consciousness is the spin-off product of the execution of planned conduct also makes sense. The argument, however, becomes convoluted regarding the significance of language to the execution of plans. A system already so well-organised as to be able to generate language as one of its planned products should be able to deliver it neurally, rather than have to engage the complexities of articulation, acoustics, and phonetics. Also, the converse selective advantage to that suggested may be true, the roots of behaviour that enables signs to be used as symbols may lie in the withholding of plans.

Keywords: consciousness, language, plans, motivation, evolution, motor system.

3(28) LANGUAGE AND PLANNING: ONE MECHANISM OR TWO?
Reply to Noble on Bridgeman on Consciousness
Bruce Bridgeman
Dept. of Psychology
Kerr Hall UCSC
Santa Cruz, Ca. 95064
(408) 459-4005

bruceb@cats.ucsc.edu
Abstract: Noble suggests it would be more effective for plan-monitoring and plan-executing mechanisms to connect with each other directly, in the brain. I in fact hypothesized this connectionin my article. Noble's statements about language are accurate, but he has the phylogenetic developmental sequence the wrong way around. My hypothesis that language and planning share some of the same mechanisms requires that the two appear together both in phylogenesis and in ontogenesis, and this seems to be what occurs.

Keywords: consciousness, language, plans, motivation, evolution, motor system

3(32) CONSCIOUSNESS, PLANS, AND LANGUAGE:
Commentary on Bridgeman on Consciousness
David M. Rosenthal
Ph.D. Program in Philosophy
City University of New York, Graduate School
33 West 42 Street, New York, NY 10036-8099, USA

DROGC@CUNYVM.BITNET
Abstract: There is much in Bridgeman's account that I find congenial and compelling, especially appealing is Bridgeman's application of his thesis to the tie between consciousness and language. Nonetheless, I want to raise some questions about whether the tie he finds between plans and consciousness actually does hold. Not all memory and attention is conscious. Although attention and accessing of memories are required to execute plans, we need not be at all conscious of the relevant states of memory and attention. Nor need we be conscious of the objects that those acts of attention and accessed memories are about. We need not necessarily appeal to the executing of plans to explain the important tie between language and consciousness.

Keywords: consciousness, language, plans, motivation, evolution, motor system.

3(33) CONSCIOUSNESS AND MEMORY:
Reply to Rosenthal on Bridgeman on Consciousness
Bruce Bridgeman
Dept. of Psychology
Kerr Hall UCSC
Santa Cruz, Ca. 95064
(408) 459-4005

bruceb@cats.ucsc.edu
Abstract: Rosenthal makes assertions about what can and cannot happen without being conscious. Although his distinctions are informative, they do not substitute for data. We have little precise information that differentiates the immediate feeling of awareness, such as that possible for Korsakoff patients, from the later episodic memory of conscious experience. Appeals to introspection are useful starting points, but they are clearly are not to be trusted in this context. Rosenthal also asks why conscious thinking would be more efficacious than thinking that is not conscious. The answer is that the whole armamentarium of planning becomes available to conscious thought, together with episodic memory and the linguistic mediation that goes along with it.

Keywords: consciousness, language, plans, motivation, evolution, motor system

3(34) CONSCIOUSNESS AND PLANNING:
Commentary on Bridgeman on Consciousness
Max Velmans
Department of Psychology
Goldsmiths' College,
University of London
New Cross, London SE14 6NW.

MLV@GOLD.LON.AC.UK
Abstract: Bridgeman's (1992) linkage of consciousness with planning may be grouped with similar proposals by Popper (1972) and Mandler (1975). But which, if any, of these proposals are correct? Before an evaluation can be undertaken it is necessary to specify the relationship of consciousness to any given candidate process unambiguously. Bridgeman's thesis is that consciousness has some special link with planning, however, the nature of this link is not explicit. Only when this conceptual clarification has been achieved will it be appropriate to turn to the question of whether consciousness relates more closely to planning than to perception, volition, choosing, remembering, responding, and so on.

Keywords: consciousness, language, plans, motivation, evolution, motor system.

3(35) CONSCIOUSNESS: WHAT'S THE USE?
Reply to Velmans on Bridgeman on Consciousness
Bruce Bridgeman
Dept. of Psychology
Kerr Hall UCSC
Santa Cruz, Ca. 95064
(408) 459-4005

bruceb@cats.ucsc.edu
Abstract: Velmans (1992) questions the necessity of consciousness for mental functions, considering consciousness to be a state rather than a process i.e. a result rather than a cause. If the introspection of consciousness is the result of an episodic memory system that engages plans, the question of function loses much of its meaning. Only plan execution has a function, not its concomitant consciousness. If this conception of consciousness is a form of epiphenomenalism, so be it. Unlike the epiphenomenalism of traditional philosophy of mind, this epiphenomenalism echoes a real system with a real function. It is this epiphenomenon that defines our mental life.

Keywords: consciousness, language, plans, motivation, evolution, motor system

3(36) ESSENTIALISM AND CONSCIOUSNESS:
Commentary on Bridgeman on Consciousness
Gerald S. Wasserman
Dept. of Psychological Sciences
Purdue University
West Lafayette IN 47907-1364

codelab@psych.purdue.edu
Abstract: Brigman's idea about the evolution of consciousness is attractive firstly because it postulates that consciousness is the product of a seamless evolutionary path which began with fundamental mechanisms and secondly because human language is presented as a continuation along this path. However, the idea is less an explanation of consciousness than it is an interpretation of some of the essential properties of consciousness. I would urge that our rapidly advancing knowledge of the neural mechanisms described by Bridgeman should lead us to see them as a good place to search for the roots of consciousness, rather than as an answer to the problem of consciousness.

Keywords: consciousness, language, plans, motivation, evolution, motor system

3(37) ON DEFINING CONSCIOUSNESS:
Reply to Wasserman on Bridgeman
Bruce Bridgeman
Dept. of Psychology
Kerr Hall UCSC
Santa Cruz, Ca. 95064
(408) 459-4005

bruceb@cats.ucsc.edu
Abstract: Just about everything that Wasserman (1992) says is important and accurate. Perhaps, following Wasserman's strategic advice, the best course at present is to concentrate on tracking down plans in the hope that this leads eventually to the several forms of consciousness.

Keywords: consciousness, language, plans, motivation, evolution, motor system

3(38) THE DISSOCIATION OF CONSCIOUSNESS
AND THE CONTROL OF BEHAVIOR
Commentary on Bridgeman on Consciousness
Philip David Zelazo
Dept. of Psychology
Yale University
P.O. Box 11A Yale Station
New Haven, CT 06520

zelphid@yalevm.bitnet
Abstract: There is clearly a relation between consciousness and planned action, this has been recognised since the time of Aristotle. Many of our plans are conscious; the execution of those plans often requires conscious activity, and much of our conscious activity is involved in the goal-directed control of action. In so far as he attempts to explain the phylogenetic evolution of consciousness, Bridgeman seems to be looking in the right place; an account of the evolution of consciousness that emphasizes its connection to behavioral consequences. The assimilation of communication to planned behavior more generally would also seem to be promising. However, there are a number of reasons to believe that the connections that lie at the crux of Bridgeman's account are less straightforward than he caimss.

Keywords: consciousness, language, plans, motivation, evolution, motor system

3(39) THE CO-DEVELOPMENT OF CONSCIOUSNESS AND PLANNING
Reply to Zelazo on Bridgeman on Consciousness
Bruce Bridgeman
Dept. of Psychology
Kerr Hall UCSC
Santa Cruz, Ca. 95064
(408) 459-4005

bruceb@cats.ucsc.edu
Abstract: Zelazo claims the target article fails to differentiate between planning and the executions of plans, on the other. These two concepts are in fact differentiated along with other stages. Zelazo identifies a further ambiguity: executing plans cannot be synonymous with consciousness if plans can sometimes be executed without the experience of consciousness. I agree, the memory for conscious experience requires storing the event in an episodic memory. Zelazo's second line of reasoning differentiating planning and consciousness is the data on executive functions, showing that having a conscious plan does not necessarily mean being able to execute it. I agree that the interrelationships among the influences I descibe are less straightforward than those described in the target article, which represents only a start in this direction.

Keywords: consciousness, language, plans, motivation, evolution, motor system.

3(41) WOULD YOU CHOOSE UNREMEMBERED PAIN?
Commentary on Bridgeman on Consciousness
Steven Reidbord
Department of Psychiatry
Box CSN-0984 UCSF
San Francisco CA 94143

reidbord@macpsy.ucsf.edu
Abstract: Bridgeman appears to equate epistemology with ontology, but these are different issues. While memory recall may be needed to know or PROVE conscious experience, it does not COMPRISE conscious experience. Conscious experience matters greatly even in the absence of the memory needed to prove that it occurred. An account of consciousness must not establish an epistemology so stringent that ontology gets lost in the process.

Keywords: consciousness, language, plans, motivation, evolution, motor system.

3(42) VARIETIES OF CONSCIOUS EXPERIENCE
Reply to Reidbord on Bridgeman on Consciousness
Bruce Bridgeman
Department of Psychology
Kerr Hall UCSC
Santa Cruz, Ca. 95064

bruceb@cats.ucsc.edu
Abstract: The immediacy of current awareness or sentience runs up against a paradox of time: that the present is a moving knife-edge with no duration and therefore no content. Even the simplest stimuli and the most direct neural events require time to be coded. The psychological present must therefore extend into the past. Our feeling of rich awareness escapes the paradox by using a working memor. The contrast between the properties of this memory and the long-term episodic memory creates the contrast between immediate and reflective consciousness. Conscious experience and memory are inextricably intertwined from start to finish. Experience requires memory and is made meaningful by other memory. And different aspects of consciousness are supported by different kinds of memory with distinct neurological organizations.

Keywords: consciousness, language, plans, motivation, evolution, motor system

3(43) CONSCIOUSNESS AND CULTURE
Commentary on Bridgeman on Consciousness
Horace Barlow
Physiological Laboratory
Downing St
Cambridge CB2 3EG, UK

AECP1@PHOENIX.CAMBRIDGE.AC.UK
Abstract: Bridgeman agrees that consciousness is bootstrapped by other brains but he argues that it then becomes autonomous and hence that it is possible to examine it in a single brain. If one does so one should be aware that the method can tell one little or nothing about important aspects of the object of study, which stems from the fact that the most important aspect of consciousness is that it is the medium through which the social culture within which we live is transmitted and developed. If you study consciousness in an isolated brain, you will be studying a biological phenomenon divorced from its extraordinarily potent role in our evolution.

Keywords: consciousness, language, plans, motivation, evolution, motor system

3(47) CONSCIOUSNESS CONFOUNDED
Commentary on Bridgeman on Consciousness
Katharine McGovern & Bernard J. Baars
The Wright Institute
Berkeley, CA 94710

baars@bayes.stanford.edu
Abstract: Bridgeman's effort to say something new or useful about consciousness and language is flawed. His major theoretical construct, the "plan," on which he depends to develop his arguments is defined in at least four different ways. Consciousness, which is variously described as the operation of the plan-executing mechanism or the outcome of its operation, is relegated to a purely epiphenomenal status with no psychological functions ascribed to it. Finally, Bridgeman's discussion of perception as deriving from the "plan-monitoring mechanism" leaves much that is known about perception unaccounted for.

Keywords: consciousness, language, plans, motivation, evolution, motor system

3(48) CONSCIOUSNESS AND SIMULATION
Commentary on Bridgeman on Consciousness
Neil W. Rickert
Department of Computer Science
Northern Illinois University
DeKalb, IL 60115

rickert@cs.niu.edu
Abstract: Bridgeman (1992) has presented some interesting ideas about the nature of consciousness. I discuss them from a computational point of view, but the concept of consciousness is difficult to grasp, so I will phrase my comments in terms of thought rather than consciousness, since there is at the very least, a strong relationship between the two.

Keywords: consciousness, language, plans, motivation, evolution, motor system, computer science, artificial intelligence, thought.

3(50) MENTAL LIFE AS SIMULATION
Reply to Rickert on Bridgeman on Consciousness
Bruce Bridgeman
Kerr Hall UCSC
Santa Cruz, Ca. 95064

bruceb@cats.ucsc.edu
Abstract: The idea of brain processes as simulations can unify the interpretation of a number of seemingly diverse mental functions. Rickert (1992) proposes to extend the idea of planning to trying out ideas, even in the absence of "a coherent plan." Plans need not be coherent or even rational. They need only include a sequence of actions determined in advance. The idea of thinking as simulation is consistent with my original conception, and extends it in a useful direction.

Keywords: consciousness, language, plans, motivation, evolution, motor system

3(53) PLANNING TO PLAN: ITERATIVE BRAIN FUNCTION
Reply to McGovern/Baars on Bridgeman on Consciousness
Bruce Bridgeman
Department of Psychology
Kerr Hall UCSC
Santa Cruz, Ca. 95064

bruceb@cats.ucsc.edu
Abstract: I defined a plan as an internally held image of an intended achievement. The plan can then control a sequence of actions to achieve a goal. This property of plans is not inconsistent with the definition. I also pointed out that plans motivate behavior. Again, there is no inconsistency, just an elaboration. McGovern and Baars ask whether we decide unconsciously which of several plans might be used to achieve a goal. The answer is, yes: plans pop into our heads like the "aha" phenomenon of Gestalt psychology. There is an iterative process, however, that can use internal speech to develop plans. If consciousness is a result of the planning mechanisms at work, then the functions of consciousness are the functions of plans and planning. In my interpretation, the perception of sequences is handled not by the plan-executing (motor) mechanism, but by a separate plan-monitoring (sensory) mechanism that functions both to monitor one's own progress in a plan and to interpret sequences of outside events. Simpler perceptions become conscious to the degree that they engage the working memory needed to consolidate sensory events into interpreted experiences.

Keywords: consciousness, language, plans, motivation, evolution, motor system

3(54) HAS CONSCIOUSNESS BECOME A SOLUBLE PROBLEM?
Commentary on Bridgeman on Consciousness
J. T. Enright
Neurobiology Unit, A-002
Scripps Institution of Oceanography
University of California
La Jolla, CA. 92093
(619) 534-3784

jenright@ucsd.edu
Abstract: Bridgeman (1992) advocates "a new psychology of plans," however, the time is not yet ripe for a frontal attack on the problem of consciousness, the necessary tools and insights are not yet available and the problem is not yet tractable. Bridgeman mentions several regions of the brain where he proposes that plans are synthesized, modified and executed, but how might one recognize in those areas the plan-executing events that constitute consciousness, and distinguish them from other unconscious forms of information processing? With what alternative possibilities should the hypothesized mechanism be confronted, in order to design critical experiments? If no answers are forthcoming this new definition leaves consciousness as a problem that is, at present, just as intractable as before. And so psychologists and neurophysiologists will, I think, continue for some time yet to chip away at the edges of the consciousness problem.

Keywords: consciousness, language, plans, motivation, evolution, motor system